Introduction.
One of the main tasks of economic theory is to explain the outcomes
of a decentralized economy. The best developed model which
addresses this problem is the by now standard, Arrow-Debreu,
general equilibrium model (further referred to as the standard
Walrasian model). Almost nobody has ever claimed that this model
gives a realistic description of a decentralized economy, and the
founders of this theory have never had any pretension to realism
(see Punzo [1988] for a survey, but also Negishi [1962] for an
exception). Hence, in this note we will restrict our attention to
the, relatively safe, domain of pure theory. In that field, then,
frequently something as the following is claimed. Take an economy
consisting of a set of autonomous agents with given preferences and
endowments. Let these individual agents freely choose their
demands, given the prices, then it can be proved that, having made
only the appropriate assumptions about the primitives
of the economy, there exists an equilibrium in which the choices of
all these agents may be realized. Note that this would be a
remarkable result, as each individual agent was considering only
his own preferences and endowments. In this note we address
the question whether such a claim is right.
An answer to this question is of
theoretical importance. Within the social sciences there is a
continuous debate about the appropriate basic subject-matter of
social theory. To simplify matters in economics terms, there is a
spectrum of possibilities ranging from the micro to the macro level
(see e.g. Giddens & Turner [1987] for a systematic overview). Now,
Walrasian economists claim that they can explain both the behavior
of individual agents and the overall outcome of their actions in a
decentralized economy, by adopting the methodological point of view
of the first of the extremes of the spectrum, that is by starting
their analysis at the level of autonomous subjects. An autonomous
subject is an agent whose set of possible actions and outcomes is
not predetermined by any form of a given structure, a set of rules,
a certain context, or anything that transcends the level of the
agents. Moreover, a theory which considers the overall outcome of
these individual actions is a theory based upon autonomous subjects
if and only if this overall outcome is, in one way or another,
thought to depend only upon the behavior of these agents. If the
Walrasian claim would be right, then that would be an important
theoretical achievement.
But an answer to the question is also
of practical importance. For example, a popular idea among both
economists and policy makers is that the purely theoretical,
mathematical economics, although dealing with unrealistic and
abstract models, has at least proved that a decentralized economy
is optimal, as far as there are no real world complications in the
form of external effects, public goods, increasing returns, etc.
Such an idea may lead both researchers (e.g. Hahn [1982]) and
policy makers to focus attention exclusively upon the problem of
such complications. However, if the Walrasian claim would be
unjustified, then statements about the acceptability or optimality
of decentralized trade cannot be defended at all by referring to
theoretical results concerning Walrasian models.
We will argue, however, that the
claim is not right. In section 2 we describe the Walrasian point of
view on how to model a decentralized economy. We expose the
structure not only of the standard Walrasian model, but also of
fixed price models, imperfectly competitive models and temporary
equilibrium models. Although that is not an exhaustive survey of
models which exhibit the same structure, it will suffice to
indicate the implications and limitations of the Walrasian approach
to the modeling of a decentralized economy, and to evaluate the
claim in section 3. There we argue that the structure of Walrasian
models is such that the Walrasian claim is inconsistent, and that
one cannot consider these models as ideal representations of
decentralized economies. In section 4, by discussing some other
Walrasian views, we anticipate some possible criticisms of
Walrasians who will be in disagreement with the analysis of the
previous sections. In section 5 we conclude by indicating some
possibilities of future developments of economic theory. We argue
that a different methodological point of view, paying attention
explicitly to the interaction between individual agents in a
decentralized economy, is important.